Support for Democracy
Robert Mattes, School of Government and Public Policy, University of Strathclyde, Oxfordre Politics (25/06/2018)
https://doi.org/10.1093/acrefore/9780190228637.013.622
Summary
With the worldwide wave of democratization, scholars interested in the preservation of the new democracies dusted off old theories of regime maintenance. While commonly sharing the assumption that democracy requires democrats, researchers proceeded in different directions, depending on their image of the ideal democrat. Today, we know a great deal about who supports democracy, and why. However, the state of our knowledge is incomplete at the point where it matters the most. As might be expected in any emerging area of research, different sets of scholars based their research instruments on contrasting understandings of what it means to be a democrat, and how democrats are best identified and measured. More importantly, they proceeded from differing understandings and underspecified theories as to why democrats are important, how many are needed, and how they actually affect the level and stability of democracy. Thus, while the intuition that democracy requires democrats is strong, the actual state of the evidence is still mixed, at best.
Keywords: public opinion, public support, democracy, democratization, democratic consolidation
Subjects: Political Behavior, Political Psychology, Public Opinion
Democracy Requires Democrats
With the worldwide wave of democratization that began in 1974 and escalated after 1989, scholars interested in identifying the factors most likely to preserve new democracies began to dust off old theories of regime maintenance, which had identified the fundamental importance of citizen attitudes and values. Based largely, if implicitly, on these approaches, a new and extensive body of public opinion research then developed. For all its internal differences, this research is based on the assumption that, in addition to committed elites and well-functioning political institutions, ordinary citizens are a key part of the democratic equation. Democracy, in other words, requires democrats. Or as Rose and colleagues (1998, p. 8), put it:
If institutions are the ‘hardware’ of democracy, then what people think about these institutions constitutes the ‘software’ of democracy ─ and software is just as important as hardware in making a system work. Constitutional reforms are lifeless or irrelevant if they do not have the support of the people.
Beginning with the first analyses of these transitions to democracy, teams of scholars carried out a range of public opinion projects in the new multiparty systems of Southern Europe (Gunther et al., 1986; Morlino & Montero, 1995), Latin America (Booth & Seligson, 1994; Lagos, 1997), Central and Eastern Europe (Barnes & Simon, 1998; Evans & Whitefield, 1995; Rose et al., 1998), the Soviet Union (Finifter & Mickiewicz, 1992; Gibson et al., 1992; Miller et al., 1993), East Asia (Chu, Diamond, & Shin, 2008; Dalton & Shin, 2006), sub-Saharan Africa (Bratton et al., 2005), South Asia (deSouza, Palshikar, & Yadav, 2008), and North Africa and the Middle East (Jamal & Tessler, 2008). Ongoing global survey projects, such as the World Values Survey, also retooled their questionnaires to include new items on democracy. While they frequently differed in approach, nearly all of the studies assessed the extent of favorable citizen attitudes toward democracy and the factors that led people living in new, potentially fragile democracies to embrace democratic values, institutions, and processes.
Through this body of research, we now know a great deal about who supports democracy, and why. However, the state of our knowledge is incomplete at the point where it matters the most. As might be expected in any emerging area of research, different sets of scholars based their research instruments on contrasting understandings of what it means to be a democrat, and how democrats are best identified and measured (see also Shin, 2017). More importantly, scholars proceeded from differing understandings and underspecified theories of why democrats are important, how many are needed, and how they actually affect the level and stability of democracy. Thus, while the intuition that democracy requires democrats is strong, the actual state of the evidence is still mixed, at best.
What Kind of Democrat?
More than half a century ago, Easton (1957) proposed that a political system would maintain itself only when it established an equilibrium between the “inputs” generated by society and the “outputs” delivered by that system. Societal inputs comprise not only a vast range of “demands,” consisting of what society’s members want the system to do (or not do), but also “supports” offered by members of society, consisting of cooperative or assistive actions or favorable orientations. One type of support is offered by members of society on an instrumental basis when they are satisfied with what they get from the system (the outputs). Easton called this “specific support.” However, because virtually all political systems encounter periods of stress caused by economic recession or political scandal, they would not last very long if they were based only on this type of support. Thus, Easton reasoned that there must also be a form of support based not on short, or even medium-term, satisfaction, but on a belief that the existing system of making, executing, and enforcing societal rules is legitimate—or what he called “diffuse support.” For a political regime, widespread diffuse support would consist of an attitudinal consensus around the fundamental “rules of the game” that provides a “reserve of support that enables a system to weather the many storms when outputs cannot be balanced off against input of demands. It is kind of support that a system does not have to buy with more or less direct benefits” (Easton, 1975, p. 273).
Easton’s theory, however, tells us only that a political system needs diffuse support; it does not consider the nature of those attitudes or the nature of the political system. Thus, public opinion scholars have also linked their work to a related argument advanced by Eckstein (1961, 1966). Eckstein hypothesized that the success of a given system depended on the “congruence” of its specific basic operating principles and current popular values. In other words, particular regimes require particular political cultures; or, conversely, some particular cultures are unsuitable to support particular regimes. Thus, Eckstein reminded us that the content of the culture matters. “Congruence theory” sees the waves of democratization that began in the 1970s as the consequence of a disjuncture between the norms of the old regime and its institutions and those of the mass public. The key research question in new democracies is whether the value structure that questioned and de-legitimated the former authoritarian or totalitarian regime is sufficient to legitimate and consolidate the new democracy.
The congruence argument, however, also has important shortcomings. It does not tell us much about the content of the values that are congruent with a democratic system. In other words, if a democracy requires democrats, what kind of democratic citizen is needed? A review of the most important contributions to the literature reveals at least four distinct conceptions, or images, of the kind of democrat needed to sustain democracy and make it work. The first three emphasize different types of values, while the fourth focuses on the role of regime preferences.
Mrs. Dahl?
Scholars falling within the first tradition have focused on identifying and measuring a set of basic psychological predispositions or personality attributes conducive to democracy, which when combined together might make up a composite ideal citizen. We could call this citizen “Mrs. Dahl.” In Polyarchy (1970) and in Democracy and Its Critics (1989), Dahl argued that democracy (or his term for modern representative democracy, polyarchy) depends on a distinctive set of citizen beliefs (held at least by the most active citizens): the effectiveness of government in solving major problems, the legitimacy of democratic institutions and participation, competition combined with the possibility of cooperation with other citizens, democratic authority relationships between government and governed, and trust in political leaders and fellow citizens.
A long line of important political culture studies have embodied this approach, including Almond and Verba’s (1963) foundational study of political culture and democracy, and studies by Eckstein (1966), Pye and Verba (1965), and Inkeles and Smith (1974). While these works were produced at different times, they all focus on psychological or personality attributes, including moderation, accommodation, tolerance, pragmatism, interpersonal trust, efficacy, cooperation, and willingness to compromise. Dahl’s work was an even more explicit influence on Gibson et al.’s study of political attitudes in the Soviet Union of the late 1980s. Gibson et al. defined a democrat as someone:
who believes in individual liberty and who is politically tolerant, who holds a certain amount of distrust of political authority but at the same time is trustful of fellow citizens, who’s obedient but nevertheless willing to assert rights against the state, who views the state as constrained by legality, and who supports basic democratic institutions and processes. (Gibson et al., 1992, p. 372)
The typical research design used in this approach consists of a series of questions that ask respondents to agree or disagree with statements about democracy, democratic processes, and politics more broadly. Gibson, for instance, used 19 different items to measure six subdimensions of democratic values: tolerance, valuation of liberty (versus order), willingness to assert rights/ rights consciousness, support for dissent, support for independent media, and support for democratic elections, and found that these attitudes cohere into a general syndrome of democratic beliefs (Gibson et al., 1992).
Mr. Putnam?
A second image of the kind of democrat required by democracy focuses on the element of interpersonal trust contained in the Dahlian framework, but adds a specific set of social structures and behaviors related to civic associations. Based on Putnam’s Making Democracy Work (1993), the ideal democrat is not someone with a democratic personality, but a “socially capitalized man.” Social capital consists of connections among citizens that create norms of cooperation and trust, and together constitute a resource on which people and communities can draw for public benefit. Thus, “Mr. Putnam” is a person with a deep sense of trust in his fellow citizens, and who belongs to and is involved in multiple community organizations.
In contrast to the Dahlian approach, Putnam’s theory is a macrolevel, rather than microlevel, theory. As Norris (2002) put it, “We can be higher or lower in social capital, but not you or I.” Thus, a socially capitalized society is characterized by a dense matrix of civic organizations in which citizens have overlapping membership, and an extensive sense of interpersonal trust that creates a resource on which neighborhoods, communities, and countries can draw to “make democracy work.” In particular, social capital helps produce public goods and solve the “free rider” problem, particularly in the area of collective action. Norms of cooperation and trust “spill over” into forms of civic participation, such as working with others, contacting representatives, and monitoring government. All of these activities make government more accountable, help government bodies like the police or social welfare services do their jobs, or even help provide services when official structures do not work.
While specific country studies experimented with ways to measure interpersonal trust as a multifaceted concept with multi-item scales, longitudinal analyses of social capital in the United States and comparative cross-national studies have tended to rely on the widely critiqued single standard question on generalized interpersonal trust in “others.”1 This question was asked in the United States as early as 1972, and subsequently was included in many other opinion studies, as were other typical questions on membership in a range of civic associations and groups.2
Mrs. Maslow?
The third image of the ideal democrat retains the focus on interpersonal trust, but embeds it within a broader range of attitudes variously called “post-modern,” “self-expression,” “liberty,” or “emancipation” values. Based fundamentally on the work of Inglehart, this approach proceeds from an attempt to provide a deeper theoretical basis to the longstanding claim of modernization scholars that economic growth, increasing levels of education, and an expanding network of communication push political systems toward liberalization and democracy in a uniform way.
Inglehart (1977) identified two key mechanisms by which economic change leads to political change. First, the “scarcity hypothesis” contends that people value what is in least supply. Pointing to Maslow’s (1943) hierarchy of needs, Inglehart argued that, where people encounter regular shortages of basic survival needs, they will focus little if any attention on the form of government and support any political system that seems to meet those needs. Only when, and where, people’s basic and intermediate physiological security needs have been satisfied will they come to emphasize higher-order needs, or what Maslow called “self-actualization,” such as a clean environment, racial and gender equality, sexual emancipation, free speech, liberty, and democracy. Second, the “socialization hypothesis” asserts that people’s fundamental values are learned during adolescence, solidify in early adulthood, and change only modestly thereafter. The simple linear view of modernization and democratization might conclude that the reason wealthier countries are more democratic is that people adopt more democratic values as they become wealthier. But the socialization mechanism means that developing societies will democratize only once they have a sufficiently large number of citizens who have grown up free of material need. Thus, while economic change drives value change, the key differences within a country will occur between generations.
Inglehart challenged the linear view of early modernization theory in another way. Along with Welzel, he concluded that because the shift from traditional to industrial economies leads to greater hierarchy, bureaucratization, centralization of authority, and a shift from traditional to secular values, modernization can lead either to democracy or to totalitarianism (as in Germany, Italy, and the Soviet Union). Rather, it is the shift from industrial to post-industrial service economies that generates greater emphasis on individual autonomy and self-expression values and produces a sufficiently widespread number of “self-actualized” democrats, who not only demand democracy but also make democracy work through increased rates of political participation, often featuring new or unconventional forms.
Employing a variety of question items and scales from the World Values Survey, which was originally designed to measure older concepts of “materialism” and “post-materialism,” Inglehart and Welzel’s many publications presented critics with a moving target as their scales of self-expression and emancipation values changed rapidly, if marginally. However, at its core, the self-actualized person was generally someone who is happy and satisfied a with life, trusts other people, and values equality over patriarchy, participation over physical or economic security, and tolerance over conformity. However, while Inglehart was interested in creating national-level indices that describe the extent of self-expression or emancipation values, scholars have raised a steady chorus of criticism of the microlevel structure of these macrolevel indices (see Alemán & Woods, 2016; Lane & Wagschal, 2012; Seligson, 2002; Teorell & Hadenius, 2006).
Mr. Churchill?
While the first three approaches built upon one another to some extent, the fourth approach marks a significant departure. Rather than attempting to identify and measure values conducive to democracy, it focuses on popular regime preferences. Rose (1997) criticized the previous approaches by asking whether there was any reason to expect to find large numbers of citizens with democratic personalities, high levels of social capital, or self-actualization in the new democracies of the 1990s. In contrast to what they called the “idealist” value-based approach, Rose and Mishler (2001) proposed a more limited, “realist” theory of democracy and public opinion. That is, the ideal citizen in a new democracy is not someone who loves democracy or is democratic in personality, but more simply is someone who sees democracy as the least bad alternative. This is what Rose called the “Churchill hypothesis,” a play on Churchill’s famous 1947 address to the British House of Commons in which he observed: “No one pretends that democracy is perfect or all wise. Indeed, it has been said that democracy is the worst form of government except all those other forms that have been tried from time to time.” Thus, their image of the ideal, or at least sufficient, democrat required in a new democracy is “Mr. Churchill.” And support for democracy is conceived not as the holding of particular values but as a choice between competing regime types.
This approach gained wide appeal because it also cohered well with Linz and Stepan’s influential study of democratization in which they built public opinion into their definition of a consolidated democracy (1996, pp. 14−15). Besides the absence of antidemocratic or secessionist groups, and the presence of universal adherence to democratic norms and practices, democracy becomes consolidated, they argued, only “when a strong majority of public opinion . . . holds the belief that democratic procedures and institutions are the most appropriate way to govern collective life, and when support for antisystem alternatives is quite small or more-or-less isolated from pro- democratic forces.” That is, consolidation occurs when democracy becomes “the only game in town” (p. 6). However, as appealing as this definition was for public opinion researchers, it was not completely satisfying, since Linz and Stepan failed to specify how much support was enough, although Diamond (1999) provided a degree of greater precision, reckoning that consolidation required support from “all significant elites,” and 75% of the mass public.
Rather than enquiring how close or distant people fall from some ideal state of mind, the measurement strategy in this approach asks respondents about alternative regimes, especially those with which they have had some actual experience. Furthermore, rather than requiring respondents to agree or disagree with statements about democracy, the typical research strategy frames questions to offer respondents explicit alternatives to democracy. Perhaps the most widely used question, first asked in surveys in Southern Europe (Morlino & Montero, 1995), offers respondents three distinct statements to the effect that “democracy is always preferable,” an “authoritarian” or “nondemocratic regime is sometimes preferable,” or “it doesn’t matter to a person like me.”3 These types of questions are often complemented by, or combined with, questions on alternative nondemocratic regimes. The original formulation began by telling respondents that “Our current system of government is not the only one that this country has had,” and then asked them whether they supported or opposed various nondemocratic alternatives.4 Question items based on the Churchillian approach now constitute the backbone of the measurement of support for democracy in the various regional barometer surveys, also known as Global Barometer Surveys (see Denemark et al., 2016). It is also important to note that a set of questions apparently framed in this approach was built into the World Values Survey. However, slight differences in how these items were framed and worded have produced drastically differing results.
Satisfied Democrats?
It is worthwhile to take note of one additional line of analysis that focuses on the results of a question on “satisfaction with democracy.”5 Properly understood, this and similar questions provide a useful measure of popular evaluations of the political and economic performance of the democratic system (or what Easton called outputs). Indeed, support and satisfaction with democracy have distinct empirical etiologies (Mattes & Bratton, 2007), and distinct consequences (Gunther et al., 2007). However, while no scholar has used satisfaction with democracy as an indicator of diffuse regime support, many have used it as a measure of Easton’s notion of “specific support,” or as a form of legitimacy more broadly (Aarts et al., 2014, 2016; Anderson et al., 2005; Fuchs et al., 1995; Listhaug et al., 2009).
This assumes that satisfaction is indicative of a supportive attitude. However, the use of this item to tap specific regime support conflates evaluations of regime performance with regime support, defined as the belief in the desirability of democracy as a regime. Whether support for democracy is specific or diffuse cannot be ascertained prima facie by a face validity reading of question wording, but rather through the statistical analysis of the covariation of stated support and performance evaluations. That is, just because a large number of respondents choose the response that “democracy is always preferable” does not mean on its face that the society is composed of a large number of steadfast democrats who value democracy intrinsically. If pro- democratic responses vary instrumentally in a systematic way with expressed satisfaction with “the way democracy works,” or with evaluations of presidential performance, satisfaction with the economy, or partisanship, that support is “specific” in the Eastonian sense. Conversely, if expressed support is unlinked to performance evaluations, and rather to other sociological factors, such as education or cognitive sophistication, that support can be seen as “diffuse” in the sense that those people support democracy intrinsically.
Thus, questions on satisfaction with democracy, or any other evaluations of the performance of democratic institutions, have a clear role to play as indicators of output satisfaction, or the “supply of democracy” (Bratton et al., 2005; Mattes & Bratton, 2007), but they should not be used as a measure of support, whether diffuse or specific. Indeed, while this literature assumed that positive replies indicated specific support, negative replies (when combined with democratic support) have been used by Norris (1999, 2011) and others (Klingemann, 1999; Qi & Shin, 2011) to identify “dissatisfied” or “critical democrats,” who are seen to play a positive role in improving the quality of democracy.
Do People Want Democracy?
Research designs in either the Dahlian or Maslowian approach use multi-item indices to tap underlying mental constructs and yield average decimalized index scores, often expressed in standardized terms. Thus, few scholars have attempted to generate population estimates of the actual proportion of citizens with the appropriate democratic attitudes or values, but the societies that cluster at the high end of these indices invariably tend be wealthier and located in North America or Western Europe. Similarly, Norris (2002) developed a social capital index, consisting of the percentage of people who trust others and the number of organizations to which the average citizen responded, and found that wealthier and older democracies of northern Europe, North America, Australasia (but also South Korea, Taiwan, and the Dominican Republic) had relatively high levels of social capital.
When viewed through a Churchillian lens, most people in most countries say they support democracy and prefer it to other regime types. However, even in this more limited, “realist” sense, scholars obtain very different estimates depending on how survey questions are worded and framed. Using the responses to the questions in the World Values Survey, some scholars have concluded that support for democracy is uniformly high across the globe (Inglehart & Welzel, 2005; Klingemann, 1999, 2014; Norris, 2011; Welzel, 2013).6 In the median country, for example, Inglehart (2003) reported that more than 9 in 10 people said that “having a democratic political system” is either a “good” or a “very good way of governing this country.” Thus, he concluded that survey questions that use the “D-word” (democracy) or that ask about support for alternative types of political regimes generate “lip service” support for a “motherhood” concept. Others reached the same conclusion, though for a different reason. They point to survey-based investigations into how people understand democracy and conclude that popular understandings of the concept vary so widely that we cannot be sure of what people are saying when they answer questions about democracy (Carlin & Singer, 2011; Shin, 2017; Shin & Kim, 2016).
However, a review of responses to the Churchill-type questions in 57 societies on four continents covered by the Global Barometer Surveys between 2004 and 2007 yielded profoundly different results, with large cross-national and cross-regional variation (Denemark et al., 2016). For instance, while 85% of Botswanans and 84% of Venezuelans said that “democracy is always preferable,” just 39% of Malagasy and 24% of Pakistanis said so. And although 82% of Southern Europeans supported democracy by the early 1990s (and still do), just 43% of South Asians did in 2005 surveys. And when the authors examined responses to questions about authoritarian alternatives to democratic government, such as a one-party state, military rule, or presidential dictatorship, support for democracy (measured as the rejection of these alternatives) was even lower in many places. Indeed, a surprisingly large number of people in many post-authoritarian societies approve of, or at least fail explicitly to reject, authoritarian alternatives to democracy. For example, 63% of Sri Lankans and Nepalese and 26% of Jordanians actively approved of a strong leader who does not have to bother about elections, while nearly half of Bangladeshis (45%) and Pakistanis (49%) approved of military rule (for similar conclusions about the uneven nature of support in East Asia, using a relatively different battery of items, see Shin & Kim, 2016).
The same large differences in estimates of, and thus conclusions about, public attachment to democracy in many countries are shown in Figure 1. The figure compares the most recent responses to two questions asked by different survey projects in the same set of 40 countries between 2010 and 2014. While both questions explicitly refer to democracy, they are framed quite differently. Evidently, survey items and constructs that use the “D word” do not automatically tap invalid “motherhood” responses to socially desirable concepts. While the World Values Survey item that asks people to agree or disagree with a positive statement about democracy yields consistently high levels of agreement (over 70% in each country, and over 80% in most), the Global Barometer Surveys question that explicitly offers respondents simple, but apparently important, alternatives, such as “whether or not we live in a democracy does not matter to a person like me,” finds levels of support that are consistently lower, sometimes by more than 30 percentage points, and that vary widely, from a high of 80% to a low of 36%.
Are Publics Becoming More or Less Supportive?
As important as it is, the extent of popular support for democracy takes us only so far. Perhaps a more important question is whether the scope of public support (as variously measured) has increased over time, or at least not contracted. The most recent analysis of Global Barometer Survey results (Denemark et al., 2016) suggested that, despite cross-national differences, the trajectories of public attitudes were moving in the “right” direction in all but one of the democratizing regions for which longitudinal data were available. Public support for democracy rose very rapidly in Southern Europe in the 1980s and has remained at very high levels. Support for democracy and rejection of authoritarian rule also increased over time — though more modestly — in Central and Eastern Europe, Latin America, and sub-Saharan Africa. In East Asia, however, support for democracy declined in four of the six countries included in the first two rounds of the East Asia Barometer. Furthermore, in analyzing the answers to World Values Survey questions in 49 countries from 1995 to 2014, Steenekamp and Du Toit (2017) found that while support for democracy (“having a democratic political system” is a “very” or “fairly good way of governing this country”) remained very high (around 9 in 10), support for expert rule, military rule, and presidential dictatorship all increased by 4 to 5 percentage points.
In sharp contrast to this picture of global stability, Foa and Mounk (2016, 2017) claimed to find “signs of deconsolidation” in Americans’ and West Europeans’ responses to these and other World Values Survey questions. The proportions who thought democratic rule was a “bad” way of governing the country, for instance, or who supported nondemocratic alternatives, such as military rule, while still at low levels, had risen sharply, while the proportions who said it was “important” to live in a democracy had fallen. Moreover, Foa and Mounk claimed, both trends were far more pronounced among the most recent generations. Given the antidemocratic trends that had been taking place in places like Turkey, Philippines, Poland, and Hungary, combined with the British electorate’s vote to leave the European Union and the American public’s election of Donald Trump, these claims attracted both widespread attention and sharp scholarly response. Critics charged that the authors had made selective use of questions and response categories, and that the absolute sizes of any declines, and of age differences therein, were quite modest (Alexander & Welzel, 2017; Goa, 2015; Voeten, 2017). Others pointed out that the reported age differences were likely due to long-apparent life-cycle effects, rather than generational erosion (Voeten, 2017). And while millennials did express weaker approval of democratic values in Anglo- American democracies, the trend was not consistent in other Western democracies (Norris, 2017). Indeed, Voeten (2017) found no systematic decline across a range of established democracies over a 20-year period. Perhaps the most telling response came from Alexander and Welzel (2017), who argued that the focus on the changes in percentages missed the fact that younger people are increasingly more likely than older respondents to link their support for democracy to a liberal understanding of what democracy entails (Alexander & Welzel, 2017). This reflected the more fundamental finding made by those working within the Dahlian and Maslowian approach that there have been important qualitative changes in citizens’ values over the past several decades, with citizens adopting less allegiant, and more assertive, stances toward political authority (Dalton & Shin, 2014).
Where Does Support Come From?
In contrast to economic theories of democratization, which see the demand for democracy as emanating from the poor and working class who see democracy as a tool to be used against the wealthy, almost all studies have found that support — at least in the democratizing world — is greatest among those with higher levels of education, who use news media, and have higher levels of cognitive engagement with politics. And most studies also find support to be higher in urban areas and among men. The cognitive basis of democratic citizenship can also be seen in a related finding: people who understand democracy in political, procedural, or liberal terms are more supportive, whether support is measured as regime preferences (Alexander & Welzel, 2017; Bratton et al., 2005; Mattes & Bratton, 2007; Mattes et al., 2016) or as self-expression or emancipation values (Welzel & Inglehart, 2009).
In addition, as anticipated by the Easton framework, support for democracy also tends to have a significant instrumental, or “specific,” nature to it. Yet, while the common scholarly wisdom expected support to hinge on public satisfaction with the economy (see Przeworski, 1995), a range of studies on different continents agree that the instrumental nature of support tends to be driven by political factors as much as, or more than, economic factors, including the quality of the electoral process, the level of political freedom, the level of corruption, and the trustworthiness of representative and state institutions (Bratton et al., 2005; Denemark et al., 2016; Diamond, 1999; Evans & Whitefield, 1995; Mattes & Bratton, 2007; Rose et al., 1998). This is perhaps best illustrated by the long time-series of data collected in post-authoritarian Spain, where high levels of support for democracy have endured, even in the face of two separate periods of economic crisis (1981–1982 and 2008), with sharp rises in unemployment and inflation (Gunther & Montero, 2016).
What Does Support Do?
Beyond its extent, and recent trends, the ultimate question that concerns us is whether support for democracy has anything to do with the stability or quality of a democratic political system. Unfortunately, we have no clear answer. At the micro level, there are some signs that democratic attitudes are indeed linked to potentially pro-democratic behaviors. Both Welzel (2007) and Qi and Shin (2011), for instance, found, respectively, that those who hold “liberty values” or are “dissatisfied democrats” (who support democracy but are also dissatisfied with the way it works) are more likely to sign petitions or take part in boycotts and demonstrations. However, there is no reason to conclude that those actions were necessarily taken in support of, or in defense of, democracy. Bratton et al. (2005) presented respondents with a range of potential steps that an antidemocratic leader might take against democracy, and found that Africans with higher levels of support for democracy were more likely to oppose such a leader and to say they would take specific actions to defend democracy. Yet these findings are limited by the hypothetical nature of the questions and responses.
The clearest link between democratic attitudes and pro-democratic behavior comes from an inventive study carried out by Gibson (1997). Gibson had just finished a survey of Russians’ democratic values when the Soviet military staged an unsuccessful coup. He then re-interviewed these respondents, asking them whether they had supported or opposed the coup, and whether they had taken any actions for or against it. The evidence was clear: Russians who were most supportive of democratic institutions in the original survey were much more likely to have supported the anti-putsch faction, and also more likely to report having taken some specific action in support (ranging from simply talking to someone else about the unfolding events to participating in anti-coup protests). While attitudes toward protest were the strongest predictor, democratic values were clearly linked to pro-democracy protest.
We also have evidence that attitudes toward democracy can guide voting behavior where explicit antisystem political parties exist. In their analysis of surveys carried out by the Comparative National Election Project (CNEP) in seven new democracies in Latin America and Southern Europe, Gunther et al. (2007) found that respondents who did not prefer democracy were significantly more likely to report having voted for political parties or candidates linked to the old autocratic regime (in Spain, Bulgaria, and Chile) or to explicitly antidemocratic parties (Italy). In contrast, those who were dissatisfied with democracy simply voted against the ruling party, regardless of the democratic bona fides of the party in power. Importantly, subsequent rounds of CNEP surveys could find no such link because there were no political parties in the countries under study with any tangible linkages to the old regime or explicitly antidemocratic platforms (Mattes et al., 2016).
At the macro level, there is conflicting evidence about whether aggregate public opinion is sufficiently powerful to shape the nature of the political regime. Early claims about the link between democratic stability and a peculiar mix of Dahlian personality attributes, what Almond and Verba (1963) called the “civic culture,” were inconclusive because the study was based on only five countries. At the same time, Booth and Seligson (1994) challenged this account by illustrating inconsistencies in the democratic record of Costa Rica, Mexico, and Nicaragua and their citizens’ relative levels of support for democratic processes.
Putnam’s regional comparison within Italy argued that differing civic traditions in the north versus the south manifested themselves in differing levels of social capital, which produced very different qualities of governance (Putnam, 1993). While limited to a comparison of two regions, Putnam appeared to identify a “silver bullet” that might generate effective and accountable governance, and the study had a major impact on democracy advocates and donor organizations in the mid to late 1990s, many of whom initiated new programs to “build social capital.” Norris (2002) subjected this claim to cross-national analysis and found strong macrolevel correlations between levels of social capital and subsequent levels of wealth and democracy. Yet she remained “strictly agnostic” about the causal direction between the associations, acknowledging that it was equally likely that trust is produced by wealth, and by previous democratic experience, or that they are all commonly driven by other forces, such as social modernization.
In contrast, the Maslowian image has received far more extensive cross-national testing, yet it has remained the object of continuing debate. In various studies, Inglehart and Welzel claimed that that a country’s level of “self-expression,” “liberty,” or “emancipation” values measured at a given point in time accounted for anywhere from one half to three quarters of the variance in subsequent changes in level of democracy across a large number of cases, even after controlling for factors like a country’s level of economic development and subsequent experience with democracy (Inglehart & Welzel, 2003, 2005, 2010; Welzel, 2013; Welzel & Inglehart, 2006, 2009; Welzel & Moreno, 2014; Welzel et al., 2016). Yet the name of the value index changed frequently, as did the composition of the index and overall model, as Inglehart and Welzel responded iteratively to a series of critics who argued that, once better measures of democracy, time lags, and country-specific effects were taken into account, the statistical impact of values disappeared (Dahlum & Knutsen, 2016; Hadenius & Teorell, 2005; Teorell & Hadenius, 2006). Indeed, Dahlum and Knutsen (2016) argued that the data suggested that values were a product of prior levels of democracy, rather than a cause.
A recurring theme within the Inglehart analysis has been the contention that implicit values (variously labeled) are far more important determinants of system-level democracy than explicit regime preferences. In an early analysis, for instance, Inglehart & Welzel (2003) showed that, while the proportion of respondents who told World Values Survey interviewers that “having a democratic government” would be a “bad way” to govern a country was indeed strongly related to subsequent system-level changes in the level of democracy, a country’s aggregate self- expression value score explained a considerably greater proportion of variation. Other studies also failed to find any significant impact of explicit democratic preferences, whether measured by the World Values Survey (Hadenius & Teorell, 2005; Qi & Shin, 2011; Teorell & Hadenius, 2006) or by the Barometers surveys (Fails & Pierce, 2010). Yet, as arguments evolved over time in response to critics, regime preferences have begun to make their way back into the analysis. Welzel and Moreno (2014) showed how emancipative values lead to higher levels of respondents’ desire to live in a democracy, a liberal understanding of democracy, and more critical views of democratic performance. More importantly, Welzel and Klingemann (2010) showed that “substantive demand for democracy” (those who both prefer a democratic regime and hold emancipative values) explains three quarters of subsequent levels of democracy. Most recently, Alexander and Welzel (2017) claimed that countries with larger proportions of citizens who prefer democracy and have a liberal understanding of democracy, and who hold liberal sexual values, are more democratic and more liberally democratic.
From outside the Maslowian perspective, Qi and Shin (2011) demonstrated that preferences for democracy and rejection of authoritarianism matter, but only when that support is matched with a sense of dissatisfaction with the way democracy is working. Using a sample of 46 “transitional regimes” that excluded established Western democracies, they found that the proportion of dissatisfied democrats (counted as those who scored above the median on both a scale of support and rejection, and below the median on a scale of satisfaction with democracy and confidence in government, legislature, and political parties) was strongly related to subsequent levels of democracy, and had an even stronger impact on the extent of change in the level of democracy, even after controlling for a range of country-level factors, including that country’s self- expression value score. Thus, they concluded, effective demand for democracy only arises from dissatisfied democrats. While congruence theory may account for (in)stability, “it is a sense of democratic deficit or deprivation that can directly trigger citizen participation in such democratic movements. Critical democrats experience such a sense of democratic deficit” (Qi & Shin, 2011, p. 256).
Conclusion
So are democrats critical to democracy, and if so, how? There is some tantalizing microlevel evidence that democrats do in fact do the types of things that help to defend and deepen democracy. Furthermore, at the macrolevel, there is a hint that aggregate democratic preferences, leavened with liberal values, a liberal understanding of democracy, or a critical view of democratic performance, propel democracy forward. However, at this point, the safest answer is that the jury is still out.
Several different issues need to be addressed before a definitive conclusion can be drawn. First, we need to think more deeply about which image of the ideal democrat is appropriate. To do this, we need greater clarity about whether mass support for democracy is necessary for democracy to occur or endure (in line with congruence theory) or whether it simply increases the probability that democracy will occur or deepen (a theory of supply and demand). Moreover, we need to be clearer about when we expect public attitudes to matter: do they de-legitimate autocracies and push them toward democracy, deepen established democracies, or defend vulnerable democracies against autocratic entrepreneurs — or all of the above? We also need deeper thinking about who needs to be democratic. It seems obvious that levels of support should not only be high, but also broad, cutting across key partisan, economic, and social cleavages, but it could easily be true that a new democracy can withstand lower levels of support so long as support is concentrated among the most active and articulate opinion leaders, or among the supporters of governing parties.
Most importantly, there is far too little evidence of exactly how support translates into democracy. Do democrats drive the process of democratization by signing petitions or by joining boycotts, protests, or social movements? Or, do they give life to existing democratic systems through civic engagement and political participation? Or, do they protect democracy against erosion or breakdown by not voting for antidemocratic candidates, or by defending democracy through forms of peaceful collective action? Or — as most of our models implicitly assume — do citizens deter elite attempts to curtail democratic practice simply by holding pro-democratic orientations and creating a climate in which strategic politicians see little space to retract democratic practice? Finally, regardless of whether support for democracy is necessary for democracy or only increases its probability, in neither case does anyone see pro-democratic public attitudes as sufficient. Thus, we also need to pay attention to how support interacts with other elite or institutional factors. For example, can high levels of mass support compensate for weak elite preferences for democracy (Mainwaring & Perez-Linan, 2013), or must they both be high? And are mass attitudes more influential when filtered through legislators elected on the basis of a personal vote in single-member districts, or through disciplined political parties elected by proportional representation? Alternatively, can strong court systems or activist civil society organizations compensate for low levels of public support? Depending on our answers to these questions, it may not be very useful to continue regressing a given measure of democracy, or of change in democracy, on a single set of mass values or preferences across a large number of countries with vastly differing histories of democracy, and at different stages of democratic development. Rather, testing these possibilities will require the inclusion of new sets of variables and might require radically different designs, examining differing sets of cases, and using differing time lags. Until then, it is likely that our understanding of public support for democracy will remain weakest at the spot where it matters the most.
References
Aarts, K., Thomassen, J., & Van Ham, C. (2014). Globalization, representation, and attitudes toward democracy. In J. Thomassen (Ed.), Elections and representative democracy: Representation and accountability. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Aarts, K., Van Ham, C., & Thomassen, J. (2016). Modernization, globalization and satisfaction with democracy. In C. Van Ham, J. Thomassen, K. Aarts, & R. Andeweg (Eds.), Myth and reality of the legitimacy crisis: Explaining trends and cross national differences in established democracies (pp. 37–58). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Aleman, J., & Woods, D. (2016). Value orientations from the World Values Survey: How comparable are they cross nationally? Comparative Political Studies, 49(8), 1039–1067.
Alexander, A., & Welzel, C. (2017). The myth of deconsolidation: Rising liberalism and the populist reaction. Journal of Democracy. Retrieved from https://www.journalofdemocracy.org/online-exchange-%E2%80%9Cdemocratic- deconsolidation%E2%80%9D <https://www.journalofdemocracy.org/online-exchange-%E2%80%9Cdemocratic- deconsolidation%E2%80%9D>.
Almond, G., & Verba, S. (1963). The civic culture: Political attitudes and democracy in five nations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Anderson, C., Blais, A., Bowler, S., Donavan, T., & Listhaug, O. (2005). Losers’ consent: Elections and democratic legitimacy (pp. 311–332). New York: Oxford University Press.
Barnes, S. & Simon, J. (Eds.). (1998). The post-communist citizen. Budapest: Erasmus Foundation and Institute for Political Science of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences.
Booth, J., & Seligson, M. (1994). Paths to democracy and the political culture of Costa Rica, Mexico and Nicaragua. In L. Diamond (Ed.), Political culture and democracy in developing countries (pp. 99–130). Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers.
Bratton, M., & Mattes, R. (2001). Support for democracy in Africa: Intrinsic or instrumental? British Journal of Political Science, 31(3), 447–474.
Bratton, M., Mattes, R., & Gyimah-Boadi, E. (2005). Public opinion, democracy and market reform in Africa. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Carlin, R., & Singer, M. (2011). Support for polyarchy in the Americas. Comparative Political Studies, 44(11), 1500–1526.
Chu, Y., Diamond, L., Shin, D. C. (2008). How East Asians view democracy. New York: Columbia University Press.
Dahl, R. (1971). Polyarchy. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Dahl, R. (1989). Democracy and its critics. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Dahlum, S., & Knutsen, C. H. (2016). Democracy by demand? Reinvestigating the effect of self-expression values on political regime type. British Journal of Political Science, 47, 437–461.
Dalton, R., & Shin, D. C. (Eds.). (2006). Citizens, democracy and markets around the Pacific Rim: Congruence theory and political culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dalton, R., & Shin, D. C. (2014). Reassessing the “civic culture” model. In R. Dalton & C. Welzel (Eds.). The civic culture transformed: From allegiant to assertive citizens (pp. 91–115). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Denemark, D., Mattes, R., & Niemi, R. (2016). Growing up democratic: Does it make a difference? Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers.
DeSouza, P., Palshikar, S., & Yadav, Y. (2008). Surveying South Asia. Journal of Democracy, 19(1), 84–96.
Diamond, L. (1999). Developing democracy: Towards consolidation. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Easton, D. (1957). An approach to the analysis of political systems. World Politics, 9(3), 383–400.
Easton, D. (1965). A systems analysis of political life. New York: John Wiley and Sons.
Easton, D. (1975). A re-assessment of the concept of political support. British Journal of Political Science, 5(4), 435–457.
Eckstein, H. (1961). A theory of stable democracy. Princeton, NJ: Woodrow Wilson School of Public and International Studies.
Eckstein, H. (1966). Division and cohesion in democracy: A study of Norway. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Evans, G., & Whitefield, S. (1995). The politics and economics of democratic commitment: Support for democracy in transition societies. British Journal of Political Science, 25(4), 485–513.
Fails, M., & Pierce, H. N. (2010). Changing mass attitudes and democratic deepening. Political Research Quarterly, 63(1),
174–187.
Finifter, A., & Mickiewicz, E. (1992). Redefining the political system of the USSR: Mass support for political change.
American Political Science Review, 86, 857–874.
Foa, R. S., & Mounk, Y. (2016). The democratic discontent. Journal of Democracy, 27(3), 5–17.
Foa, R. S., & Mounk, Y. (2017). The signs of deconsolidation. Journal of Democracy, 28(1), 5–15.
Fuchs, D., Guidorossi, G., & Svensson, P. (1995). Support for the democratic system. In H. D. Klingemann & D. Fuchs (Eds.), Citizens and the state (pp. 323–353). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gibson, J. (1997). Mass opposition to the Soviet putsch of August 1991: Collective action, rational choice, and democratic values in the former Soviet Union. American Political Science Review, 91(3), 671–684.
Gibson, J., Duch, R., & Tedin, K. (1992). Democratic values and the transformation of the Soviet Union. Journal of Politics, 54, 329–371.
Goa, J. (2015, December 2). Debunking the myth that millennials are ushering in the end of the Western world. Washington Post.
Gunther, R., & Montero, J. R. (2016). Southern Europe: Elite-led culture change. In D. Denemark, R. Mattes, & R. Niemi (Eds.), Growing up democratic: Does it make a difference? (pp. 25–62). Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers.
Gunther, R., Montero, J. R. S., & Torcal, M. (2007). Democracy and intermediation: Some attitudinal and behavioral dimensions. In R. Gunther, J. R. Montero, & H. J. Puhle (Eds.), Democracy, intermediation and voting on four continents (pp. 29–76). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gunther, R., Sani, G., & Shabad, G. (1986). Spain after Franco: The making of a competitive party system. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Hadenius, A., & Teorell, J. (2005). Cultural and economic prerequisites of democracy: Reassessing recent evidence. Studies in Comparative International Development, 39(4), 87–106.
Inglehart, R. (1977). The silent revolution: Changing values and political styles among western publics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Inglehart, R. (2003). How solid is mass support for democracy: And how can we measure it? PS: Political Science & Politics, 36(1), 51–57.
Inglehart, R., & Welzel, C. (2003). Political culture and democracy: Analyzing cross-level linkage. Comparative Politics, 36(1), 61–80.
Inglehart, R. & Welzel, C. (2005). Modernization, cultural change, and democracy: The human development sequence. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Inglehart, R., & Welzel, C. (2010). Changing mass priorities: The link between modernization and democracy. Perspectives on Politics, 8(2), 5510567.
Inkeles, A., & Smith, D. (1974). Becoming modern: Individual change in six developing nations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Jamal, A., & Tessler, M. (2008). Attitudes in the Arab world. Journal of Democracy, 19(1), 97–110.
Klingemann, H. D. (1999). Mapping political support in the 1990s. A global analysis. In P. Norris (Ed.), Critical citizens: Global support for democratic governance (pp. 31–56). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Klingemann, H. D. (2014). Dissatisfied democrats: Democratic maturation in old and new democracies. In R. Dalton & C. Welzel (Eds.), The civic culture transformed: From allegiant to assertive citizens (pp. 116–157). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Lagos, M. (1997). Latin America’s smiling mask. Journal of Democracy, 8(3), 125–138.
Lane, J.-E., & Wagschal, U. (2012). Culture and politics. New York: Routledge.
Linz, J., & Stepan, A. (1996). Problems of democratic transition and consolidation. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Listhaug, O., Aardal, B., & Ellis, I. (2009). Institutional variation and political support: An analysis of CSES data from 29 countries. In H. D. Klingemann (Ed.), The comparative study of electoral systems. New York: Oxford University Press.
Mainwaring, S., & Perez-Linan, A. (2013). Lessons from Latin America: Democratic breakdown and survival. Journal of Democracy, 34(2), 123–137.
Maslow, A. (1943). A theory of human motivation. Psychological Review, 50(4), 370–396.
Mattes, R., & Bratton, M. (2007). Learning about democracy in Africa: Awareness, performance and experience. American Journal of Political Science, 51(11), 191–217.
Mattes, R., Munjani, S., Liddle, W., Shi, T., & Chu, Y. H. (2016). Parties, elections, voters and democracy. In R. Gunther, P. Beck, P. Magalhaes, & A. Moreno (Eds.), Voting in old and new democracies (pp. 193–229). London: Routledge.
Miller, A., Reisinger, W., & Hesli, V. (Eds.). (1993). Public opinion and regime change: The new politics of post-Soviet studies. Boulder, CO: Westview.
Morlino, L., & Montero, J. R. (1995). Legitimacy and democracy in Southern Europe. In R Gunther (Ed.), The politics of democratic consolidation: Southern Europe in comparative perspective. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Norris, P. (1999). Critical citizens: Global support for democratic governance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Norris, P. (2002). Democratic phoenix. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Norris, P. (2011). Democratic deficit: Critical citizens revisited. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Norris, P. (2017). Is western democracy backsliding? Diagnosing the risks. Journal of Democracy. Retrieved from https://www.journalofdemocracy.org/online-exchange-%E2%80%9Cdemocratic- deconsolidation%E2%80%9D <https://www.journalofdemocracy.org/online-exchange-%E2%80%9Cdemocratic- deconsolidation%E2%80%9D>.
Przeworski, A. (1995). Sustainable democracy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Putnam, R. (with Leonardi, R., & Nanetti, R.). (1993). Making democracy work: Civic traditions in modern Italy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Pye, L., & Verba, S. (1965). Political culture and political development. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Qi, L., & Shin, D. C. (2011). How mass political attitudes affect democratization: Exploring the facilitating role critical democrats play in the process. International Political Science Review, 32(3), 245–262.
Reilly, J., & Zigerell, L. J. (2012). Don’t know much about democracy: Reporting survey data with nonsubstantive responses. PS: Political Science and Politics, 45, 462–467.
Rose, R. (1997). Survey measures of democracy. Studies in Public Policy 294. Glasgow: Centre for the Study of Public Policy, University of Strathclyde.
Rose, R., & Mishler, R. (2001). Political support for incomplete democracies: Realist vs. idealist theories and measures. International Political Science Review, 22(4), 303–320.
Rose, R., Mishler, W., & Haerpfer, C. (1998). Democracy and its alternatives: Understanding post-Communist societies. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Seligson, M. (2002). The renaissance of political culture, or the renaissance of the ecological fallacy? Comparative Politics, 34(3), 273–292.
Shin, D. C. (2017). Popular understanding of democracy. Oxford research encyclopedia of politics. Retrieved from http:// politics.oxfordre.com/view/10.1093/acrefore/9780190228637.001.0001/acrefore-9780190228637-e-80 <http:// politics.oxfordre.com/view/10.1093/acrefore/9780190228637.001.0001/acrefore-9780190228637-e-80>.
Shin, D. C., & Kim, H. J. (2016). Liberal democracy as the end of history: Western theories versus Asian realities. Asian Journal of Comparative Politics, 2(2), 133–153.
Steenekamp, C., & Du Toit, P. (2017). The evolution of support for democratic regime principles and its alternatives. Journal of Public Affairs, 17(1–2), 1–12.
Teorell, J., & Hadenius, A. (2006). Democracy without democratic values: A rejoinder to Welzel and Inglehart. Studies in Comparative International Development, 41(3), 95–111.
Voeten, E. (2017). Are people really turning away from democracy? Journal of Democracy. Retrieved from https:// www.journalofdemocracy.org/online-exchange-%E2%80%9Cdemocratic-deconsolidation%E2%80%9D <https:// www.journalofdemocracy.org/online-exchange-%E2%80%9Cdemocratic-deconsolidation%E2%80%9D>.
Welzel, C. (2007). Are levels of democracy affected by mass attitudes? Testing attainment and sustainment effects on democracy. International Political Science Review, 28(4), 397–424.
Welzel, C. (2013). Freedom rising: Human empowerment and the quest for emancipation. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Welzel, C., & Inglehart, R. (2006). Emancipative values and democracy. Studies in Comparative International Development, 41, 74–94.
Welzel, C., & Inglehart, R. (2009). Political culture, mass beliefs and value change. In C. Haerpfer, P. Bernhagen, R. Inglehart, & C. Welzel (Eds.), Democratization (pp. 126–144). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Welzel, C., Inglehart, R., & Kruse, S. (2016). Pitfalls in the study of democratization. British Journal of Political Science, 46, 1–10.
Welzel, C., & Klingemann, H. D. (2010). Democratic congruence re-established: The perspective of ‘substantive’ democracy. In M. Rosema, B. Denters, & K. Aarts (Eds.), How democracy works: Political representation and policy congruence in modern societies (pp. 89–114). Utrecht: Pallas Publications.
Welzel, C., & Moreno, A. (2014). Enlightening people: The spark of emancipative values. In R. Dalton & C. Welzel (Eds.),
The civic culture transformed: From allegiant to assertive citizens. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Notes
1. “Generally speaking, would you say that most people can be trusted or that you can’t be too careful in dealing with people?”
2. “Now I am going to read off a list of voluntary organizations. For each one, tell me whether you are an active member, an inactive member, or not a member of that type of organization.”
3. “Which of the following statements do you agree with most? A) Democracy is preferable to any other kind of government. B) In certain situations, an authoritarian government can be preferable to a democratic one. C) To people like me, it doesn’t matter whether we have a democratic government or a nondemocratic government.”
4. “Our current system of government is not the only one that this country has had. Some people say that we would be better off if the country was governed differently. What do you think? A) We should return to Communist rule? B) The army should govern the country? C) Best to get rid of Parliament and elections and have a strong leader who can quickly decide things. D) A return to monarchy would be better? E) The most important decisions about the economy should be made by experts and not the government and Parliament.”
5. The original version asked in Eurobarometer read: “On the whole, are you very satisfied, fairly satisfied, not very satisfied or not at all satisfied with the way democracy is developing in our country?”
6. The World Values Survey contains several questions that are intended to measure support for democracy:
“I am going to describe various types of political systems and ask what you think about each as a way of governing this country. For each, would you say it is a very good, fairly good, fairly bad, or very bad way of governing this country? Having a strong leader who does not have to bother with parliament and elections; having experts, not government, make decisions according to what they think is best for the country; having the army rule; having a democratic system.”
“I’m going to read some things that people sometimes say about a democratic political system. Could you please tell me if you agree strongly, agree, disagree, or disagree strongly, after I read each one of them? In democracy, the economic system runs badly. Democracies are indecisive and have too much quibbling. Democracies aren’t good at maintaining order. Democracy may have problems but it’s better than any other form of government.”